Cheating
is dishonest behaviour intended to gain academic advantage. Examples of
cheating include looking at someone’s test, getting information for someone
else during a test, giving someone else information or allowing someone to copy
from your test or bringing a ‘cheat sheet’ into a test. Cheating same as
plagiarism. Plagiarism means using another’s work without giving credit card. Understanding student cheating is particularly important
given trends that show cheating is widespread and on the rise. In 1964, Bill
Bowers published the first large-scale study of cheating in institutions of
higher learning. Bowers surveyed more than 5,000 students in a diverse sample
of 99 U.S. colleges and universities and found that three fourths of the respondents
had engaged in one or more incidents of academic dishonesty. This study was
replicated some 30 years later by McCabe and Treviño (1997) at 9 of the schools
who had participated in Bowers’s original survey. Although McCabe and Treviño
observed only a modest increase in overall cheating, significant increases were
found in the most explicit forms of test or exam cheating.
As we know that some students do cheating
because their behaviour, they prefer depends on their friends when doing a test
or an exam. In general, student understanding of appropriate citation techniques
seems to have changed, and selected behaviors that students may have classified
as plagiarism in Bowers’s (1964) study do not appear to be considered
plagiarism by many students today. For example, although most students understand
that quoting someone’s work word for word demands a citation, they seem to be
less clear on the need to cite the presentation of someone else’s ideas when
the students present them in their own words. The reason why the student do
cheating because they want to finish their work easily and they do not want to
take any difficulties. In spite of Bowers’s (1964) conclusions about the
powerful influence of institutional context on student decisions to cheat, between
the 1960s and 1990 most of the research on student cheating focused on the role
of individual factors related to cheating behavior. This stream of research
revealed that factors such as gender, grade point average (GPA), work ethic,
Type A behavior, competitive achievement striving, and self-esteem can significantly
influence the prevalence of cheating (e.g., Baird, 1980; Eisenberger &
Shank, 1985; Perry, Kane, Bernesser, & Spicker, 1990; Ward, 1986; Ward
&Beck, 1990). With few exceptions, the thrust of this research has centered
on one of the most basic ethical decisions faced by college students—to cheat
or not to cheat on their academic work. Research shows that all too often these
pressures lead to decisions to engage in various forms of academic dishonesty
(e.g., Bowers, 1964; McCabe, Treviño, & Butterfield, 1999). Research also
shows that these transgressions are often overlooked or treated lightly by
faculty who do not want to become involved in what they perceive as the bureaucratic procedures designed
to adjudicate allegations of academic dishonesty on their campus (e.g., McCabe,
1993;Nuss, 1984; Singhal, 1982). Students who might otherwise complete their
work honestly observe this phenomenon and convince themselves they cannot
afford to be disadvantaged by students who cheat and go unreported or
unpunished.
Another reason do cheating that can bring
impact to effect of honor codes on students. Although Bowers (1964), McCabe and
Treviño (1993), and others have documented the powerful effect of such codes,
how and why they work when students on code campuses face the same grade
pressures as their peers else where is not well understood. Gaining additional
insight into this question was the subject of a qualitative study of college
cheating reported by McCabe et al. (1999). McCabe et al analyzed data from more
than 1,700 students at 31 U.S. colleges and universities, approximately half of
which employed an honor code. Data for this study were collected in the form of
open-ended comments made by students at the end of a larger survey on college
cheating. Many of these comments corroborated the importance of the
institutional–contextual factors found to be related to academic integrity by
McCabe and Treviño (1993,1997). Contextual influences on cheating that were
emphasized by students included the degree to which the code is deeply embedded
in a culture of integrity; the degree to which a school has a supportive,
trusting atmosphere; competitive pressures; the severity of punishments; the
existence of clear rules regarding
unacceptable behavior; faculty monitoring; peer pressure to cheat or not to
cheat; the likelihood of being caught or reported; and class size. In
particular, the results suggest that students at honor code schools view
academic integrity in a very different way from their noncode counterparts. The
code students were less likely to cheat, were less likely to rationalize or
justify any cheating behavior that they did admit to, and were more likely to
talk about the importance of integrity and about how a moral community can
minimize cheating. Although students at both types of schools report that they
cheat and feel many different sources of pressure to cheat, honor code students
apparently do not succumb to these pressures as easily or as often as noncode
students.
Other perspectives said that cheating is
wrong. Since cheating is
obviously wrong, arguments against it (it provides an unfair advantage, it hinders learning). Asking why cheating is wrong may seem a silly question or a
gratuitous provocation. Indeed, since “just about everyone agrees that cheating
is bad and that we need to take steps to prevent it” (Kohn,2007), no question
seems warranted and no argument seems needed. Talk about cheating is then a
matter of outrage: “students STOLE a password and then they used it to CHEAT”
(Lingen, 2006), “plagiarism is WRONG no matter
what the extent” (Parmley,
2000). A. J.
Ayer would have said that a claim that cheating is wrong is just
writing ‘cheating’ followed by some
special exclamation mark Lingen and Parmley prefer capitals. A common view is that cheating is forbidden and cheaters
break a rule. For instance, the focus of
Burkill and Abbey (2004) on “regulations” and on “penalties” for “ignoring academic conventions” indicates that to them
the main reasons for students to avoid cheating are obedience to rules and
avoidance of penalties. However, Alfie
Kohn (2007) draws attention to those “cases where what
is regarded as cheating actually consists of a failure to abide by
restrictions that may be arbitrary and difficult to defend”. Breaking a rule
is illegitimate only if the rule is
legitimate. Either the rule has a rational justification and this rather than breaking a
rule makes cheating wrong, or the rule is arbitrary and there is no reason to
endorse it. In other words, cheating should be forbidden because it is
wrong, not wrong because it is forbidden. Obviously, the wrongness of
cheating should be an ethical not a bureaucratic question. As Drake (1941) pointed out, cheating can be frustrating to the
instructors, who may “interpret such behaviour as a direct affront to
themselves.” When Johnston (1991) found out that students had cheated she felt
betrayed: “how could they do this to me?”. While this may explain better than genuine
arguments why teachers dislike cheating it does not show that cheating is
wrong. It is interesting to note that this is generally not offered as an
argument in articles looking at cheating in a ‘cold’ objective way but can be found
in more personal papers, such as that of Johnston. This seems to acknowledge
that this is both a real reaction of the ‘victims’ of cheaters and not
perceived as a valid argument against cheating.
Since everything else depends on
it, the question of the wrongness
of cheating is the most important question. CHEATING AND GRADES. It is a
wide-spread error in issues of cheating to assume that cheating is obviously
wrong (Bouville,2007b; 2008b; 2008c). In particular, if one does not know why
cheating is wrong one cannot set policies that would solve the problem. LIMITS OF THE
ARGUMENT OF UNFAIR ADVANTAGE. Hall et al. (1995) found that a deep
approach to learning correlated
negatively with SAT scores; students who merely learned by rote and who
minimized their involvement or tried to get good grades without caring about
what they learnt obtained higher scores than students who sought a deeper
understanding of what they were taught. In other words, students who had
good work habits and a sound mindset that would help them succeed in the
long run received lower SAT scores —
students most likely to succeed are treated
as least desirable. Cheating undermines feedback. Passow et al. (2006) argue that “acts of academic
dishonesty undermine the validity of measures of student learning”. If teachers
do not know that there is something the students do not understand (if they cheat
it may seem that they understand) then it is impossible for them to know
whether to accelerate or slow down, on what to focus, or how to re-design their
lectures next year — in the long term, cheating hurts the students. It
also prevents teachers from providing students with relevant feedback. One should remark
that this argument is more relevant to homework than to exams (especially final
exams) because the latter are used more for grading or ranking and less for
feedback, making cheating on homework worse
than cheating on finals. Similarly, cheating on entrance exams would not be
wrong at all since these are not meant to provide any feedback at all.
In other words, this argument forces us to hold as worst the instances of
cheating that would generally be seen as mildest. This is not surprising since feedback
(either way) is not genuinely seen as of prime importance; that
grades matter more is clearly reflected in the far greater
importance given (by both students
and teachers) to exams compared to homework. Cheating undermines
learning. A more important issue with cheating is that it can directly get
in the way of learning. For instance, students who copy homework assignments
instead of doing them themselves will not learn what they should. Likewise, having a book
in one’s lap does not have the same didactic impact as studying for an exam.
For cheaters to be punished because cheating hinders learning. Cheating on this
assignment must hinder learning. One should remark that it may be the absence
of cheating, rather than cheating, that
hinders learning. For instance, Stephens (2005) found that “only 18 percent [of
high school students] believed that ‘working on an assignment with other
students when the teacher asked for individual
work’ was cheating”. This is because “students regarded this forbidden collaboration
as furthering their knowledge and understanding, and therefore saw it as an act
of learning
rather than a form of cheating”
(also see Kohn, 2007).
Cheating is disliked to a great extent because it breaks a rule
and because teachers take it as a personal offense. However, for cheating to be
wrong one must justify the rule forbidding cheating. And the fact that the teacher dislikes what a student did does not necessarily mean that the
student did something wrong. There can
be an unfair advantage only when grades are used as proxies to estimate how
students will fare in the future. The
argument of unfair advantage is thus limited in its scope mostly entrance exams
and other ‘high stake’ tests. Taking cheating to be essentially a matter of
unfair advantage means that education is essentially a fight of all against all
or it means that cheating can occur (or matter) only in a few specific
situations.
References
:
Bowers, W. J. (1964). Student dishonesty and its control in
college. New York: Bureau of Applied Social Research, Columbia University.
Davis, S. F., Grover, C. A., Becker, A. H., & McGregor, L.
N. (1992). Academic dishonesty: Prevalence, determinants, techniques, and
punishments. Teaching of Psychology, 19, 16–20.
Baird, J. S. (1980). Current trends in college cheating. Psychology
in the Schools, 17, 515–522.
Eisenberger, R., &Shank, D. M. (1985). Personal work ethic
and effort training affect cheating. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 49, 520–528.
McCabe, D. L. (1992). The influence of situational ethics on
cheating among college students. Sociological Inquiry, 62, 365–374.
McCabe, D. L. (1993). Faculty responses to academic dishonesty:
The influence of student honor codes. Research in Higher Education, 34, 647–658.
McCabe, D. L., & Pavela, G. R. (1997). Ten principles of
academic integrity. The Journal of College and University Law, 24, 117–118.
McCabe, D. L., &Treviño, L. K. (1993). Academic dishonesty:
Honor codes and other contextual influences. Journal of Higher Education,
64, 522–538.
McCabe, D. L., &Treviño, L. K. (1997). Individual and
contextual influences on academic dishonesty: A multicampus investigation. Research
in Higher Education, 38, 379–396.
McCabe, D. L., Treviño, L. K., & Butterfield, K. D. (1999).
Academic integrity in honor code and non-honor code environments: A qualitative
investigation. Journal of Higher Education, 70, 211–234
Bouville, M. (2007b)
Cheating and neutralization. Available
at http://www.mathieu.bouville.name/
education-ethics/Bouville-neutralization-empiricism.pdf.
Drake, C. A. (1941) Why students cheat, Journal of Higher
Education 12, 418–420.
Name : Danar Priyambodo
Final Project
somebody told me that students' life teaches us to cheat and to find the way out even there is none! post explaines why students cheat!
ReplyDelete